Reference Material:
Freedom
and Belief by Galen Strawson (2010)
I’m
now entering a discussion on what I’ve come to see as some of the most
compelling philosophical material in the free will debate, Galen Strawson’s Freedom and Belief. In considering
Strawson’s ideas, I’ll sketch my personal positions in the debate and continue
to hit on themes from earlier posts. Let’s go.
Strawson
makes an interesting definitional move right at the beginning of the book. He
defines freedom or free will circularly:
- “to be a free agent is to be capable of being truly or ultimately responsible for one’s actions.”
- “to be capable of being truly or ultimately responsible for one’s actions is to be capable of being truly or ultimately deserving of praise or blame for them.”
- [an agent] “is capable of being truly deserving of praise and blame for its choices and actions when and only when it is capable of free choice and free action.”
At first, I was fairly dubious of this
circularity. But reconsidering this conception in light of the definitional
disagreements at the heart of the free will debate has made me more accepting,
for two reasons. I do think these definitions capture the pre-theoretical
notion of freedom that most people carry around with them. Did he make that
choice freely? Yes he did – he’s responsible for that choice, and it’s consequences.
If they’re positive, he’ll receive credit. And if not, he’ll shoulder the
blame. And rightly so – it’s only fair. After all, it was his choice. He was
free to choose either way. Doesn’t that just sound right? For me, that kind of
thinking perfectly encapsulates the folk notions of free will, responsibility,
and desert. Strawson’s definitions just codify those notions, showing their
none-too-impressive logical structure.
I’m
also partial to Strawson’s definition because it admits right up front an
equivalence that occurs everywhere in this debate. Strawson defines free agency
as responsibility bearing. To be free is to be responsible. The two are
equivalent. This equivalence is useful, and is justified, for the following
reason. Whenever we’re arguing about whether we have free will, or what does or
doesn’t constitute freedom, we’ll use thought experiments to make our case. These
thought experiments will inevitably turn on intuitions about free will under
specific circumstances – think of the intuition relied on in Frankfurt-style
cases, that Alex’s decision to vote for Doug was free. How is this intuition
explained? How can we say Alex’s decision was free? Because we would hold him
responsible. These thought experiments rely on the equivalence of freedom and
responsibility to have force. Instead of burying that equivalence in
argumentation, Strawson lays it bare from the start.
I
now want to give a brief sketch of Strawson’s central argument. It goes
something like this:
- No one is truly responsible for how they are (e.g. their character and motivation).
- People act the way they do because of how they are.
- Therefore, no one is truly responsible for acting the way they do.
- To be free is to be truly responsible, but we aren’t truly responsible, so we aren’t free.
I must say up front that I think this argument,
or something quite like it, is basically correct. Strawson thinks 1) is true
(and I agree) because to be truly responsible for how one is, one must have
consciously chosen to be that way – consciously chosen based on some set of
reasons or desires. But then such reasons or desires are part of how one is, so
one must have consciously chosen those as well. The resulting infinite regress
undercuts the possibility of true self-determination. Here again we encounter
infinite regress issues in trying to identify the locus of agency, the self. 2)
to me seems obviously true. It seems obviously true if you conceive of humans
as purely physical systems – that system acts the way it does because of how it
is (together with the laws of nature). It seems equally true if you view humans
from the normal, high-level, mentalistic perspective – that person chose the
way they did because they desired the likely outcome, or were afraid, or
thought it most prudent, etc. 3) and 4) seem to be rather basic logical
deductions. What could be simpler?
Of
course, many philosophers disagree, and much ink has been spilled over such
disagreement. I’ve already expressed by aversion to the dialectic at this
level. I think Strawson’s work is especially valuable because he offers a
perspective on freedom that steps outside of that dialectic by analyzing what
he calls the phenomenology of freedom. That will be the subject of my next
post.